The Torch Magazine,
The Journal and Magazine of the
International Association of Torch Clubs
For 87 Years
A Peer-Reviewed
Quality Controlled
Publication
ISSN Print 0040-9440
ISSN Online 2330-9261
Spring
2014
Volume 87, Issue 3
Origins of
Chinese Philosophy
by C.
Walter Clark
In
the distant past, in the territory
watered by the Yellow and Yangzi
rivers, Chinese civilization was
born. By Chinese historical
reckoning, the time in question
extended from the late "Spring and
Autumn" era (722-481 BCE) through the
"Warring States" era (481-221
BCE).
What would one day become China was
then divided into a number of
independent states. A strong
myth of a single civilization under a
single ruler in possession of
"Heaven's Mandate" existed, but the
reality was political division.
Capital cities of independent states
attracted a growing intellectual
class, members of which adhered to one
or another teacher and traveled about
from one state to another, offering
their services as officials or
advisers. In Chinese history, it
is called the period of "100 Schools
of Thought."
The name is an exaggeration, but there
were in fact many schools. Most
analyses of Chinese philosophy in the
classical period focus on four:
Confucianism, Moism, Taoism, and
Legalism, each with its own major
figures.
Confucius, whose approximate dates are
550-479 BCE, was a teacher. It
is uncertain whether he wrote
anything; what we know of his
teachings comes from the texts left by
his students, whom we might even call
his disciples.
When asked what might be done to bring
about social order and good
government, Confucius said, "rectify
the names"— that is, endow existing
institutions with moral purpose,
causing them to become what ideally
they should be. His
philosophical justification for this
recommendation was the concept of li,
which may be translated as "right
conduct" or "proper norms of social
behavior." Confucius said "the
standard of right is the cultivation
of each class of people in its proper
course." His teachings were
meant for gentlemen, i.e., educated
males. The masses in society
would benefit by emulating the example
of their betters, such emulation
being, in his view, natural.
Confucius said: "In observing their
proper course, men look upward."
A second important Confucian concept
was an ethical ideal called ren,
usually translated as "human
heartedness," a virtue existing at
least as potential in each human
being. Gentlemen were encouraged
to cultivate this virtue in
themselves; through their example, it
would be absorbed by the masses. The
practice of ren at the highest level,
the level of the ruler, would foster
"human heartedness" throughout
society. Again, quoting from
Confucius: "The prince [ruler] is the
wind; the common people, the grass;
and the grass bends in the direction
of the wind." For Confucius,
history provided the finest examples
of good government and social order.
He and many others in his day believed
that during a Golden Age in the
distant past, sage kings ruled
benevolently and everyone in society
benefited. This ideal society
might be reconstructed or at least
emulated in the present.
Confucius attracted a following, some
of whom became teachers, and these in
turn gathered students of their own,
so the teachings of the master endured
and spread and were changed. The two
best-known disciples of Confucius were
Mengzi (Mencius) and Xunzi.
Mencius was born more than 100 years
after the death of Confucius, Xunzi
more than 150 years after; changed
circumstances likely accounted for
some of the differences in philosophy
between Confucius and these two of his
disciples, since, in general,
conditions worsened during that
time.
Mencius represented the idealist wing
of Confucian thought, Xunzi the
realist wing.
Mencius differed from his master in
important ways. For Confucius,
legitimate authority was based on
Heaven's Mandate, a concept
originating in an ancient text called
the Book of History, written to
justify the fall of the ancient Shang
Dynasty and its replacement by the
Zhou Dynasty in about 1100 BCE.
According to the Book of History,
Heaven elected or commanded men to be
rulers over the tribes of the world.
When the Shang kings, who had once
been wise and benevolent rulers, grew
cruel and degenerate, Heaven called
upon Zhou chieftains to overthrow the
Shang. Confucius's
interpretation of this idea had held
only that legitimate government
required Heaven's mandate; Mencius
went further, arguing that Heaven's
will derived from the people.
Heaven "sees with the people's eyes
and hears with the people's ears," he
wrote. He also stated that "The
People are the most important element
in kingship; next comes the spirits of
the grain; and the prince is of the
least importance." In brief,
Mencius believed that government
should function for the people and
with the consent of the people.
Xunzi, the other great Confucian
disciple, writing some fifty years
after the death of Mencius in
political, economic and social
circumstances that continued to
deteriorate, adopted a realist rather
than an idealist perspective. Xunzi
rejected Mencius's view that men were
by nature good; the chief quality of
human nature was not its inherent
goodness, as Mencius taught, but its
weakness. Left unguided, people
gravitated from one superstition to
the next. Men were born with two
qualities, desire and intelligence,
and social discord arose because, in
his words, "desires are many but
things are few." What was needed
therefore was greater social control,
which required a strong state. His
policy recommendations required both
the carrot and the stick. Carrot
recommendations included promotion of
rituals, music, and education, plus
appropriate welfare measures.
Stick recommendations included
establishing clear rules of behavior
and harshly punishing those who failed
to follow the rules. Put simply,
Xunzi believed the essential purpose
of government was to regulate men's
desires. Students of Xunzi were among
the founders of the Legalist School,
examined below.
Moism
Between the lifetime of Confucius and
those of his disciples Mencius and
Xunzi, the decadent tendencies in
government and society that Confucius
deplored worsened, and a new and
important school of thought emerged,
associated with the philosopher Mozi.
Little is known about the man Mozi,
but it is generally accepted that he
was born to low social status and may
have been an artisan or
craftsman. He had no ties to
officialdom but manifested impressive
mastery of traditional culture.
What we know of his thought we derive
from the Book of Mozi, which
survives only in part.
In contrast to Confucianism, Moism was
not simply a school of thought but an
organized movement, supported by its
own religious-military organization
and headed by a supreme master.
We may assume that the initial supreme
leader was Mozi himself. Mozi
was explicitly critical of several
intellectual rivals, but he directed
his most telling polemical attacks on
Confucianists, whom he condemned for
their skepticism regarding Heaven and
spiritual beings, their fatalism, and
their preoccupation with ritual.
Mozi believed the order of society
recommended by Confucianists to be too
static. The rituals they emphasized
purposely illustrated existing
differences between classes and
perpetuated those differences.
In the Confucian view, Mozi argued,
there was no room for ambition and
social mobility.
At the heart of Mozi's thought is the
concept of "universal love," which he
presents as a utilitarian
doctrine. He argued that in the
state of nature, the wills of men
differed, and the more men, the more
conflicting wills. Mozi was what
we in the West would call a
"Hobbesian," after the 17th-Century
English philosopher Thomas Hobbes, who
argued that human beings were wholly
selfish and that society in the state
of nature was "a war of every man
against every man . . . and the life
of man [was] solitary, poor, nasty,
brutish and short." Mozi had a
similar view, concluding that creating
a peaceful and orderly society out of
such conditions required a strong
ruler, a ruler not responsible to the
people but to a higher order, to
Heaven or God.
Good government, according to Mozi,
required conformity and control.
What the virtuous ruler thought right,
all must think right. Proper
government functioned to keep order
and to punish deviants. He
acknowledged the possibility of errant
rulers whose misdeeds might deserve
punishment, but punishment for rulers,
he believed, had to come from the
deity, not from the people.
The strategy Mozi designed for
achieving his ideal government
required an organized movement with a
strong leader and a disciplined band
of followers. In its
organization and practices, the
movement would serve as a model of the
ideal order. Communal living
would be practiced, and life would be
egalitarian and austere. It
would be an arbitrarily imposed
manifestation of "universal
love."
The philosophy of Mozi is highly
religious, with Heaven portrayed as a
loving sovereign on high. Heaven
willed that men love one another, and
since men did not by nature love one
another, religion might function as an
exemplary motivating force. Both
religious and political sanctions, he
believed, were necessary to what he
saw as the two basic functions of
government: keeping order and
punishing evil.
Mozi taught that human beings were
selfish and contentious in the state
of nature; thus individuals must be
persuaded or, if necessary, forced to
subordinate their interests to the
interests and welfare of the
community. His ideal political
order was a kind of anti-aristocratic
absolutism and, perhaps, a theocracy.
Taoism
Next
to Confucianism, the most important
and influential native Chinese
philosophy was Taoism. While
Confucianism emphasizes hierarchy,
duty and social responsibility, Taoism
invites individuals to flee
conventional and mundane limitations
on the human spirit. Confucian
texts are often dull and moralistic;
early Taoist writings are mystical and
poetic, full of wit and paradox.
Yet in the history of Imperial China,
from 221 BCE to 1911 CE, Confucianism
and Taoism came to seem not so much in
opposition as they were
complementary. In Imperial
China, it was expected that
Confucianism would direct the mind of
the scholar-official in his
bureaucratic duties and social
presence, while Taoism, in his private
chamber or mountain retreat, would
draw him to the intoxicating beauties
of nature and spirit.
Two great thinkers are identified with
the founding and early development of
Taoist philosophy: Laozi and
Zhuangzi. Laozi, whose name
means "old master," with the notion of
"venerable" implied, may not have been
a genuine historical figure, but the
Tao-te Ching, one of the shortest yet
most provocative and inspired works in
all of Chinese literature, came to be
accepted as representative of his
thought. The quietness,
mysticism and love of paradox that
distinguish this work probably
represent not the thinking of a single
philosopher, but very old strains in
Chinese thought.
Tao-te Ching proposes a
philosophy of government and way of
life for the ruling class, the only
class of people who could read its
pages. Its teaching is based
upon a great underlying principle, the
Tao or Way, which is the source of all
being, governor of all life, both
natural and human. It is the
first principle of life itself and
therefore indescribable, as is
asserted in the very first entry in
the Tao-te Ching:
The
Tao that can be told of is not the
eternal Tao;
The name that
can be named is not the eternal name.
Nameless, it is
the origin of Heaven and earth;
Namable, it is
the mother of all things.
Always
nonexistent, that we may apprehend its
inner secret;
Always existent,
that we discern its outer
manifestations.
These two are
the same;
Only as they
manifest themselves they receive
different names.
That they are
the same is the mystery.
Mystery of all
mysteries!
The door of all
subtleties! (de Bary, Chan, and Watson
53)
In
the Laozi or Tao-te Ching,
dyadic opposites such as male-female,
dark-light, weak-strong appear
frequently, and the usage favors soft
over hard, passive over active, even
perhaps female over male. The
style of the Laozi—a
combination of very old adages or
cryptic sayings, often in rhyme—is
unlike that of the works of other
schools of thought in early Chinese
philosophy. Mixing poetry with
prose, and its statements are laconic
and paradoxical. These features
may explain the work's tremendous
popularity and influence through the
centuries. Over time many
important elements of Taoist teaching
were absorbed into Confucianism and
later Chinese Buddhism.
The second great early Taoist
philosopher was Zhuangzi, about whom
we know little. Sima Qian, the
great historian of the second century
BCE, provides us with only a few
facts: that Zhuangzi once was an
official, that he was a contemporary
of Mencius, and that he wrote a work
of more than 100,000 words, which was,
according to Sima Qian, "mostly
fable." Yet in the ranks of
early Taoist philosophers, only Laozi
is better known.
The central theme of Zhuangzi is
freedom. To one extent or
another, all philosophers of the
Warring States Era addressed the
question, how is man to live in a
world dominated by chaos, suffering
and absurdity? Most philosophers
answered with some concrete plan of
action. Both Confucius and Mozi,
for example, recommended social,
political and ethical reforms.
Zhuangzi did not. He believed
that both man-made ills (war, poverty,
injustice) and natural ills (disease
and death) were ills only because men
recognized them as such. Men, he
believed, had come to hold a diseased
and fear-inspired view of life, which
he illustrates using a macabre
metaphor about a leper woman who,
"when she gives birth to a child in
the deep of night, rushes to fetch a
torch and examine it, trembling with
terror lest it look like
herself." But how is one to
persuade the leper woman herself that
disease and ugliness have no real
validity? Not an easy
task. Yet Zhuangzi's message
called for individuals to free
themselves from the world's realities.
While most philosophers appealed to
the political and intellectual elite
of the day, seeking to have their
recommendations translated into
policies, Zhuangzi's recommendations
seemed designed for those seeking
spiritual relief.
He taught using paradoxical anecdotes
and seemingly nonsensical remarks,
possibly trying to jolt the mind into
an awareness of a truth outside the
pale of ordinary logic.
Certainly he employed in his writings
that deadliest of weapons against all
that is pompous, staid and holy:
humor. The parable of "The Cicada and
The Wren," in Arthur Waley's
translation, will serve as example:
There
are birds that fly many hundred
miles without a halt. Someone
mentioned this to the cicada and the
wren, who agreed that such a thing
was impossible. "You and I
know very well," they said, "that
the furthest one can ever get even
by the most tremendous effort is
that elm-tree over there, and even
this one cannot be sure of reaching
every time. Often one finds
oneself dragged back to earth before
one gets there. All these
stories about flying hundreds of
miles at a stretch are sheer
nonsense." (Waley 33)
Legalism
The
school of thought known as Legalism
was founded by Han Feizi, a student
and/or disciple of the Confucianist
Xunzi. Han Feizi's philosophy
was eclectic, containing elements from
several of the so-called Hundred
Schools of Thought. From a
philosopher named Shen Dao he borrowed
the concept of authority (shi), which
asserted that political control
required not merely power but
legitimized power, power based on
authority. More importantly, he
adopted the philosopher Shang Yang's
doctrine of law (fa). Shang Yang
ridiculed as vain and impractical
Confucian arguments stressing moral
principles, right conduct, virtue and
the like.
Han Feizi believed three principal
causes to be at the root of the
disorder in society in his day: first,
too many people and too little food,
the deadly combination of
overpopulation and underproduction;
second, selfishness, which he believed
to be inherent in all men; and
finally, intellectual anarchy, an
excess of contrasting philosophies and
schools of thought.
Han Feizi posited that fundamentally
there were just two classes in
society, which at times he labels the
industrious and incompetent, and in
other places the useful and
idle. Farmers and soldiers were
the only two segments of society he
accepted as useful. The
incompetent or idle segment included
aristocrats, artisans in luxury
crafts, hermits, innkeepers, scholars
and moralists, soothsayers,
adventurers and philanthropists.
Han Feizi's philosophy was the
antithesis of Confucian
thinking. Rejecting ethical
values, he promoted the idea of
positive law divorced from moral and
religious sanctions. He scorned
ideals from the past, ridiculing the
belief of Confucius that there had
been a golden age when sage kings
ruled benevolently. "The
enlightened ruler," Han Feizi said,
"controls his ministers by means of
two handles alone: punishment and
favor. What do I mean by punishment
and favor?" he asks. His answer:
"To inflict mutilation and death on
men is called punishment; to bestow
honor and reward is called favor"
(30).
Although Han Feizi found little of
value in Confucianism, Moism and
Taoism proved useful to his
argument. Moism stressed the
value of uniform standards and
advocated the mobilization of society
in support of the ruler's goals.
So too did Han Feizi. From
Taoism he borrowed the concept of wu
wei, non-action, asserting that a good
ruler governed by non-action.
Han Feizi wrote:
When all are in
their proper place, then superior
and inferior may be free from
action. Let the cock herald
the dawn, let the cat catch
rats. When each exercises
his ability, the ruler need do
nothing [wu-wei]. If the
ruler tries to excel, then nothing
will go right. If he boasts
of an eye for the abilities of
others, he will invite deceit
among his subordinates. If
he is lenient and fond of sparing
lives, his subordinates will
impose upon his kind nature.
If superior and inferior try to
change roles, the state will never
be ordered. (35-36)
Han Feizi's
philosophy was pragmatic, and many of
its specific concepts proved appealing
to those in positions of power or in
pursuit of power. A scholar named
Li Si, another student of the
Confucianist Xunzi, came to be employed
by the ruler of one of the warring
states, the state of Qin. He
applied the practical, ruthless policies
of the Legalist school in serving as
chief minister to the ruler Shi Huang
Di, now remembered as China's First
Emperor. The Warring States Era
came to an end, China was unified, a
tyrannical rule was imposed on society,
and policies were undertaken to make
permanent the new ruler's control.
Writing was standardized, imperial
highways were built and made uniform,
non-legalist scholars were murdered and
their texts burned, and the population
mobilized for mammoth construction
tasks. The first
emperor's ruthless exactions year after
year exhausted the people and the
state's other resources. After
thirty-seven years as ruler of the Qin
state, Shi Huang Di suddenly died at age
49 in 210 BCE, bringing China's
first imperial dynasty to an end.
A visible hint of the scale of Qin Shi
Huang Di's undertaking is suggested by
the size of his Terra Cotta Army, parts
of which are visible today at a site
near Xian, in northwest China.
The First Emperor's
excessive demands on his subjects
fomented rebellion and several ambitious
rebel leaders emerged. One of
these, Liu Bang, eventually succeeded in
defeating or co-opting his rivals and in
206 BCE founded the Han Dynasty, which
endured (with but one major
interruption) for 400 years.
Han rulers and their
advisors found it useful to retain some
of the policies recommended by the
Legalist school, but they also
discovered the utility of incorporating
ideas and policies suggested by
Confucianism. Its doctrines generally in
keeping with the values and practices of
traditional society, it was a useful
governing philosophy in times of peace
and stability, though not in times of
economic decline, political turmoil and
war.
Thus a form of
Confucianism became the orthodox ruling
philosophy in Imperial China. It
endured and evolved, becoming the basis
for the famous Examination System used
to select qualified government
officials, its concepts and teachings
integral parts of Chinese culture.
Works Cited
de Bary, Wm.
Theodore, Wing-tsit Chan, and Burton
Watson, eds. Sources of Chinese
Tradition. NY: Columbia University
Press, 1964.
Han Fei Tzu. Basic Writings.
Burton Watson, trans. NY: Columbia
University Press, 1966.
Waley, Arthur. Three Ways of Thought
in Ancient China. Palo Alto:
Stanford University Press, 1939.
Biographical
Sketch
C. Walter Clark
C. Walter Clark is
Professor Emeritus of Political Science
at Drake University, where he taught for
35 years prior to retirement in June
1998.
Following enlistment
in the United States Air Force in 1954,
he studied spoken Mandarin in a
nine-month intensive program at the
Institute of Far Eastern Languages at
Yale University, after which he was
posted to listening stations in Taiwan
and Okinawa, monitoring mainland China's
shortwave military broadcasts.
Following discharge
from the Air Force Walter, re-enrolled
at Indiana University, earning an A.B
degree in Political Science in
1960. In that year he was admitted
to the Department's Ph.D. program, his
graduate work supported by a National
Defense Education Act fellowship in
Asian Studies. While in the
program, he began study of the Russian
language and of Russian history and
politics.
He left I.U. in 1963
to accept a teaching position at Drake
University. His teaching at Drake
included courses on China, Japan, Russia
and, beginning in the mid-1980s, the
Middle East. His Middle East
course was informed by four research and
study missions to the region between
1986 and 1992.
Walter has been a
member of the Des Moines Torch Club
since 1992. His Torch papers have
focused principally on China; one of
those papers, delivered in 1995, earned
him the Paxton Award.
©2014 by the International
Association of Torch Clubs
Return to the Home Page
|
|