The Torch Magazine,
The Journal and Magazine of the
International Association of Torch Clubs
For 88 Years
A Peer-Reviewed
Quality Controlled
Publication
ISSN Print 0040-9440
ISSN Online 2330-9261
Spring
2015
Volume 88, Issue 3
The
Trouble with Truth*
Barnet
Feingold, Ph.D.
If a statement
is true, only a fool would refuse
to believe it, and only a madman
would reject its guidance. Those
words sound self-evident. Yet what
we call truth is not all it is
cracked up to be.
Some of our
truths are shining beacons on
hills, illuminating reality and
revealing processes that give rise
to our experiences. But others
intoxicate us with illusions of
knowledge, competence, and virtue,
blinding us to dangers and
encouraging us to act in ways that
are reckless, fruitless,
destructive or cruel. An apparent
truth may be unworthy of trust.
Even the most convincing
statements may mislead us.
I respect the
law. Yet I recognize that many
laws are unjust. I love sausage.
And although I believe that some
sausage makers “answer to a higher
authority” (Con Agra Foods), I
know that all too many sausages
are medleys of the unspeakable,
best left to wither
unconsumed.
Just as veneration of law and
sausage requires us to ignore the
ways they are made, uncritical
veneration of what we view as
truth requires a kind of
blindness. For the processes by
which truth is manufactured are
often corrupt. And the products of
those processes rarely embody the
virtues we assume truths to
possess.
The subject
of this paper is apparent
truth—not truth itself; that which
humans accept as true—not the
Platonic Ideal (Kraut). When I use
the word truth, I am not referring
to that which the wise yearn to
embrace, but to that which the
arrogant embrace, thinking
themselves wise. I am not
referring to those daunting
revelations that the strong can
endure only with support, but to
those reassuring misconceptions
that lead the weak to see
themselves as strong. I am not
referring to that which science
incrementally approaches, but to
the blind alleys of scientific
fashion that masquerade as
progress. I am not referring to
that which the principled strive
to speak, but to the twaddle that,
in the mouths of the frivolous,
tastes like virtue. I am not
referring to the lightly-held
conceptions of those who struggle
to understand complex and changing
phenomena, but to the disfigured
horrors that ideologues create
when they torture bothersome facts
into compliance with their
doctrines.
Although philosophers have
proposed diverse theories of truth
(Simmons), my dictionary
(McKechnie) suggests that English
speakers call a statement true if
they view it as accurately
describing the way things are.
This simple, straightforward view
of truth is common even in the
most sophisticated circles.
According to a large-scale,
on-line survey, more doctoral
level philosophers adhere to this
view of truth than to any other
(The PhilPapers Surveys
Preliminary Survey results).
To clarify further: inspired by
Charles Sanders Peirce, when I say
that we view an assertion as true,
I mean that we would confidently
act under its guidance (Peirce).
In other words, to say we view an
assertion as true is to say that
we are convinced that it provides
us with actionable
intelligence.
Imagine that Linda hates getting
wet. Imagine that she is preparing
to take a walk in the park. As she
is about to leave her home, she
discovers that weather.com
predicts thunderstorms within the
hour. If she views that forecast
as true, she will delay her walk.
If she heads for the park anyway,
odds are that she questions the
truth of the forecast.
To view that forecast as true,
Linda must be in a particular
state of mind. First, she must
experience it as making intuitive
sense. The appearance of the sky
and the texture of the air must
make her feel that a storm is
inevitable. If, upon walking
outdoors, her intuition tells her
that pleasant weather is
approaching, she is likely to
doubt the accuracy of
weather.com’s report. Second, she
must be able to generate a
narrative that justifies her
intuition. Such a narrative might
be as concrete as “Look at the
sky! That storm is moving towards
us!” or as cerebral as
“Weather.com says that there’s a
100% chance of rain in the next
hour. Their short-term predictions
are never wrong!” Finally, she
must believe that she can defend
that narrative. If she cannot
explain why she believes it is
going to rain, or if sees her
explanation as unable to withstand
questioning, she is unlikely to
see that prediction as true
(Margolis).
What creates this state of mind?
The answer is simple. If our
experience is consistent with an
assertion, we see the assertion as
true. If it has stormed every time
the sky and the air have felt a
particular way, and if the
narrative Linda uses to justify
her intuition has consistently fit
the data and withstood criticism,
Linda is likely to become
confident that she knows when a
storm is coming.
This approach to truth may seem
unproblematic—but the processes
that create belief-consistent
experiences all too often do so by
taking advantage of flaws in the
ways we perceive and reason. There
are many such flaws. Some have
negligible effects, but all too
many engender powerful biases that
compromise reason and objectivity.
Our insensitivity to ambiguity is
one such flaw.
The ambiguity of a statement is
determined, in part, by the range
of observations that are
consistent with it. The more
ambiguous a statement is, the
broader the range of observations
that support it and the narrower
the range of observations that
challenge it. In this sense, the
prediction that a roulette ball
will land in one of the wheel’s
eighteen red pockets is more
ambiguous than the prediction that
it will land in one particular
pocket.
When we are gambling, we are aware
of this sort of ambiguity. Imagine
you are about to play high-stakes
roulette and are allowed to choose
one of three consultants to help
you place your bets. Imagine that
each potential consultant is a
certified fortune teller who has
demonstrated clairvoyance under
the scrutiny of scientists,
auditors, Las Vegas security
experts, and magicians by
correctly predicting the results
of five consecutive spins of a
roulette wheel (Carroll).
Fortune Teller “A” correctly
predicted the individual pocket
into which each ball fell.
Fortune Teller “B” correctly
predicted the color of the
pocket (red or black) into which
the ball fell. And Fortune
Teller “C” correctly predicted
that the pocket in which the
ball landed would be a
manifestation of divine will.
Most of you would choose as your
consultant Fortune Teller
“A”—the fortune teller who
successfully made the most
precise predictions—because you
both sensed and judged that his
or her predictions reflected the
greatest prescience.
This exercise is what Howard
Margolis, the late social theorist
and occasional critic of
experimental psychology, might
have called a “toy problem.” Its
stakes are trivial (indeed,
imaginary). The issue of interest
is contrived, the problem devoid
of the uncertainties,
complexities, passions and
yearnings that affect most
decision-making. It portrays an
approach to ambiguity under ideal
circumstances, but it does not
depict the way we handle ambiguity
when grappling with real dilemmas.
In a 1953 Cambridge University
address, the Austro-British
philosopher Karl Popper revealed
that he was inspired to reflect on
the distinction between science
and pseudo-science by the
insensitivity to ambiguity that
characterized the principal
intellectual movements of his time
(Popper). Popper was living in
Vienna in the years following the
collapse of the Austrian Empire,
when that city, he later wrote,
was animated by “revolutionary
slogans and ideas, and new and
often wild theories.” Among the
new and wild theories that
fascinated Popper were Einstein’s
theory of relativity, Marx’s
theory of history, Freud’s
psychoanalytic theory and Adler’s
“individual psychology.”
While all
of these theories were intriguing,
Popper felt that only relativity
theory was truly scientific.
Marx’s, Freud’s and Adler’s
theories, he suspected, resembled
myths more closely than science;
nonetheless, some attributed to
them immense explanatory power.
Popper found such attributions
troubling. Followers of Marx,
Popper said, found confirmation on
every page of the newspaper, “not
only in the news, but also in its
presentation—which revealed the
class bias of the newspaper—and
especially of course in what the
paper did not say” (Popper 34).
Popper was particularly disturbed
by the ease with which Freudians
and Adlerians formulated
conflicting explanations of the
same phenomena. He noted that if a
man pushed a child into the water,
intending to drown it, Freudians
could attribute that act to
repression, while Adlerians could
attribute it to the man’s desire
to mitigate feelings of
inferiority by proving that he
dared to commit a crime. If, on
the other hand, that same man
risked his life to save the child
from drowning, Freudians could
attribute his act to sublimation
(the transformation of the energy
of a biological impulse to serve a
more acceptable use), while
Adlerians could attribute the same
act to the man’s desire to
mitigate feelings of inferiority
by demonstrating courage (Popper
35).
In other words, the theories of
Marx, Freud and Adler were
profoundly ambiguous, enabling
adherents to view a very broad
range of observations as
supportive of their theories and
scarcely any observations as
contradictory. Their inability to
predict future events, when
combined with which they explained
past events, made them the
epistemological brethren of the
fortune teller who predicted that
the outcome of each spin of the
roulette wheel would be consistent
with God’s plan.
The nature of the evidence that
supported Einstein’s theory,
Popper noted, was quite different.
One of the predictions of
relativity theory was
“gravitational lensing”—the
bending of light by gravity.
Einstein’s theory, unlike the
theories of Marx, Freud and Adler,
made precise predictions—in this
case, a prediction about the
degree to which our sun would bend
light passing close its surface.
That prediction was all the more
daring because it conflicted with
Newton’s conceptions of space,
time and gravity, which were
supported by two centuries of
astronomical observation. Unlike
the predictions of Marx, Freud and
Adler, those of Einstein ran the
same kind of risk of being
disproven as those of the
soothsayer who repeatedly
predicted the particular slot into
which the roulette ball would
fall.
That is why Popper was intrigued
by the reactions of Einstein’s
followers when, in 1919, a solar
eclipse off the coast of Africa
made it possible to measure shifts
in the apparent positions of stars
whose light passed close to the
sun. Those measurements, it turned
out, clearly supported Einstein’s
model and would have justified
righteous euphoria among
Einstein’s supporters (Kennefick).
Yet, according to Popper, even in
the wake of those measurements,
devotees of relativity were less
passionate about the truth of
their theory than followers of
Marx, Freud and Adler were about
the truths of theirs. Of course,
Einstein’s followers were thrilled
by confirmation of his
predictions. But the passions of
the followers of Marx, Freud and
Adler were of a different order,
forged by visions of their
theories as embodiments of truths
so manifest and sublime that only
those who perversely closed their
hearts and minds could doubt them.
Popper’s observations point to a
profound irony: that ambiguity
makes beliefs less illuminating
and believers more passionate.
Recent research into the adaptive
unconscious (a modern conception
unrelated to Freud’s model) has
uncovered a mechanism that
accounts for that ironic reality.
According to University of
Virginia psychology professor
Timothy Wilson, we are more likely
to pay attention to things that
resemble what we’ve encountered
before. The more often and more
recently we’ve encountered an idea
or phenomenon, the better the
chance that our adaptive
unconscious will admit it to
conscious awareness (Wilson).
Since ambiguous ideas subsume more
phenomena than precise ideas, they
are likely to be called on more
frequently—and, on average, to
have been accessed more
recently—than more precise
notions. In addition, their
ambiguity is likely to facilitate
satisfying but spurious
explanations of our concerns,
enhancing their subjective worth.
As such, it is not hard to imagine
how our adaptive unconscious can
render ambiguity-related biases
self-reinforcing.
Of course, many characteristics
other than ambiguity interact with
vulnerabilities in human reasoning
to create “truths” that are
unworthy of that appellation
(Mahoney). But such specious
truths all have one thing in
common: they appear to provide
profound understandings of broad
swaths of reality, but they do so
only because they are consistent
with all outcomes and immune to
all challenges. They appear rich
in wisdom only because they are
devoid of content. They are
subjectively reassuring only
because they are objectively
vacuous. They appear to inform us
about the world, but closer
examination reveals that by
inducing us to accept their
opportunistic rules of evidence,
they transform our vision and our
judgment, rendering us incapable
of doubting them and addicting us
to the reassurance they provide.
Truths like these are nothing but
illusions. Submission to habits of
thought that lead us to believe
such illusions and accept their
guidance is, I propose, an
abdication of our responsibility
to strive for what Bernard
Lonergan and his admirers have
called authenticity (Helminiak
2008; Helminiak and Feingold;
Lonergan).
Yet such specious truths have too
much influence over human affairs
to be casually dismissed. They may
be the kinds of statements that
members of the Vienna Circle would
have categorized as “nonsense”
(Uebel), but they are nonetheless
compelling and consequential.
Thus, in the spirit of Alfred
Ayer’s approach to the problem of
induction (Ayer) and John Dewey’s
approach to ethics (Dewey), I
modestly propose that we appraise
such “truths” by examining their
effects.
If such truths transform us into
persons who accept them without
question, I suggest that we
evaluate them by asking
ourselves whether we wish to be
thus transformed. It is, after
all, as Bernard Lonergan
observed in Method in
Theology, “up to each of
us to decide for himself what he
is to make of himself” (Lonergan
1972).
Of course, questions like, “What do
I wish to be?” or, less
narrowly, “What should I, as a
human, wish to be?” are profound,
and all answers to such questions
controvertible. But it is possible
to reduce the intoxicating
influence of specious truths by
incorporating a few simple steps
into our evaluations, and, by so
doing, to answer these questions
less parochially, with clearer
eyes and purer hearts.
The first step when answering such
questions is to place ourselves
behind a conceptual veil of
ignorance similar to that which
John Rawls suggested we use when
making decisions about justice
(Rawls). That veil must render us
agnostic regarding the truth we’re
evaluating, the assumptions that
spawned that truth, the web of
observations and beliefs shaped by
those assumptions, and the web of
observations and beliefs the truth
in question may have inspired
(Quine and Ullian). The opacity of
that veil and the expanse it
should cover may be debatable, but
there is little question that such
a veil, however imperfect,
improves the odds that exploration
of a truth will be
informative.
Second, I suggest that we attend
to how our truths and the rules we
use to judge them affect
authenticity. That is, I suggest
that we attend to the effects of
such truths and their second-order
traditions (Popper) on how we seek
and understand information,
communicate our insights,
determine whether our insights are
accurate, and use what we know to
guide our actions. To the extent
that our truths impair those
functions, they render our
commerce with the world less
effective and impair our ability
to formulate and achieve
satisfying, worthwhile.
Finally, I suggest that we attend
to how our truths affect our
ability to create and sustain
relationships, standards of
discourse, and other norms and
institutions that support
authenticity (Feingold; Habermas;
Helminiak 2008). The struggle to
function authentically requires
unrelenting confrontation of our
limitations, our failings, and our
mortality, and is rife with
intellectual challenge and
emotional pain. And authenticity,
if achieved, is a momentary state,
as unstable as an inexperienced
mountain climber on an icy,
windswept peak. We need all the
help we can get.
These components are, I propose,
essential to any valid approach to
assessing our truths. But I doubt
that they are sufficient. I
suspect that many of you would
want to include the effect of your
truths on your chances of
achieving and sharing genuine
happiness (Haidt; Seligman).
Others would likely wish to
consider the impact of their
truths on their chances of
creating a world that supports
other heartfelt values (Haidt).
Still others, I am sure, would
find it important to attend to
other effects.
While it is unlikely that persons
of candor, intelligence, and good
will ever achieve complete and
permanent agreement about how
truths should be assessed, the
effort to do so is worthwhile, for
the stakes are high.
Whatever might allow us to see
through one another’s eyes,
however fleetingly, increases the
odds of human survival and
meaningful progress. In the
absence of an approach to
mitigating the intoxicating
effects of counterfeit truth, all
too many of us will continue to
see those whose vision differs
from our own as depraved, wicked,
or less than fully human. History
reveals the results of confident
commitment to such insular truths
to have been disastrous, leaving
us, in our millions, bound,
blinded, and, if we are fortunate,
merely bloodied.
Believers
and skeptics alike must examine
how we are shaped by the true
beliefs that may, unless
constrained, transform us into
“true believers” (Hoffer), and to
do so fearlessly, objectively, and
painstakingly. In this endeavor,
may we be guided by the spirit of
Saint Jerome, who said, “The scars
of others should teach us
caution,” and, equally, by the
spirit of Ernest Hemingway, who
said, “Call ‘em like you see ‘em,
and to hell with it.”
Note
*This paper is dedicated to the
memory of Dr. Robert Seibel, and to
his wife Barbara.
Works
Cited
Adler, A.
(1964). The Individual Psychology
of Alfred Adler. H. L.
Ansbacher and R. R. Ansbacher
(Eds.), New York: Harper Torchbooks.
Ayer, A. J.
(1936). Language, Truth and
Logic. London, UK: Victor
Gollancz, Ltd.
Carroll, B.
(2012, September 15). Randi
$1,000,000 paranormal challenge.
Retrieved from The Skeptic's
Dictionary :
http://www.skepdic.com/randi.html
Con Agra
Foods. (2012, September 14).
The Hebrew National Story: More
Than 100 Years of Premium
Products . Retrieved from
Hebrew National Kosher Meat
Products:
http://www.hebrewnational.com/history/100-years.jsp
Dewey, J.
(1920). Reconstruction in
Philosophy. New York: Henry
Holt and Company.
Einstein,
A. (1920). Relativity: The
Special and General Theory.
New York: Henry Holt.
Feingold,
B. D. (1995). The spirit and its
discontents: A perspective on
violence and evil. Paper
presented at the 103rd Annual
Convention of the American
Psychological Association.
New York, NY .
Freud, S.
(1949). An Outline of
Psychoanalysis. J. Strachey
(Trans. and Ed.), New York: W. W.
Norton & Company.
Habermas,
J. (1990 [1983]). Moral
Consciousness and Communicative
Action. Cambridge, MA: The
MIT Press.
Haidt, J.
(2006). The Happiness
Hypothesis. New York: Basic
Books.
Haidt, J.
(2012). The Righteous Mind.
New York: Pantheon Books.
Helminiak,
D. A. (2008). Spirituality for
our Global Community: Beyond
Traditional Religion to a World
at Peace. Lanham, MD: Rowman
& Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
Helminiak,
D. A., & Feingold, B. D.
(2011). Being authentic about
authenticity: Opportunities,
requirements, applications, and a
progress report on measurement of
a key Lonerganian notion. Studies
in Religion/Sciences Religieuses,
40(6).
Hoffer, E.
(1952). The True Believer:
Thoughts on the Nature of Mass
Movements. London, UK:
Secker and Warburg.
Kennefick,
D. (2009, March). Testing
relativity from the 1919 eclipse--
a question of bias. Physics
Today, 62(3), 37-42.
Retrieved from Physics Today.
Kraut, R. (2012, September 14).
Plato. Retrieved from The
Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy:
http://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/sum2012/entries/plato/
Lonergan,
B. J. (1957). Insight: A Study
of Human Understanding.
London, UK: Longmans, Green &
Co.
Lonergan,
B. J. (1972). Method in
Theology. London, UK:
Darton, Longman & Todd.
Mahoney, M.
J. (2004). Scientist as
subject: The psychological
imperative (rev. ed.).
Clinton Corners, NY: Percheron
Press.
Margolis,
H. (1987). Patterns, Thinking,
and Cognition: A Theory of
Judgment. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Marx, K.
(1977 (originally published
1859)). A Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy.
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
McKechnie,
J. L. (1983). Webster's New
Universal Unabridged Dictionary,
deluxe 2nd edition. New
York: Simon and Schuster.
Peirce, C.
S. (1931-1958). Collected
Papers (8 vols.). Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Popper, K.
R. (1962). Conjectures and
Refutations: The Growth of
Scientific Knowledge. New
York: Basic Books.
Quine, W.,
& Ullian, J. (1978). The
Web of Belief. New York:
McGraw-Hill.
Rawls, J.
(1971). A Theory of Justice.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap
Press.
Seligman,
M. E. (2002). Authentic
Happiness. New York: Free
Press.
Simmons, K.
(2006). Truth. In Donald M.
Borchert (Ed.), Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (2nd ed.,
Vol. IX, pp. 534-542). Farmington
Hills, Michigan, MI: Macmillan
Reference.
The PhilPapers Surveys
Preliminary Survey results.
(2012, August 21).
Retrieved from philpapers.org:
http://philpapers.org/surveys/results.pl?affil=Philosophy+faculty+or+PhD&areas0=
0&areas_max=1&grain=coarse.
Thornton,
S. (2012, September 22). Karl
Popper. Retrieved from The
Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition),
Edward N. Zalta (ed.):
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/
win2011/entries/popper/
Uebel, T.
(2012, September 3). Vienna
Circle. Retrieved from
Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy :
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/vienna-circle/
Wilson, T. D.
(2002). Strangers to
Ourselves: Discovering the
Adaptive Unconscious.
Cambridge, MA and London, England:
The Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press.
About the
Author
Barnet D.
Feingold earned a PhD in Clinical
Psychology from the Pennsylvania
State University in 1977.
Working as a
psychologist for the US Veterans
Health Administration, he held
positions including Coordinator of
Addiction Treatment Programs,
Coordinator of the PTSD
Residential Rehabilitation
Program, Director of Psychology
Training, and Research Coordinator
in Minnesota, New York, and West
Virginia.
He has several
publications exploring the
influence of beliefs, values,
assumptions, and habits of thought
on effectiveness, intimacy, and
life satisfaction.
In recent
years, he has served as Adjunct
Professor of both Psychology and
Education at Shepherd University
in Shepherdstown, WV.
“The Trouble
with Truth” was delivered to the
Winchester Torch Club on March 13,
2013.
©2015 by the International
Association of Torch Clubs
Return to Home Page
|
|