God in
Experience
by Parker
English
A variety of
people have met what they think is God
in their own conscious experience,
their personal awareness. Some
of these people were understood by
themselves and by others to be
hallucinating, but others saw
themselves and were seen by others as
divinely inspired. For those who
believed themselves divinely inspired,
the God in their experience is
understood as independent of being
experienced—that is, He would exist
even if not experienced.
Indeed, He has caused and will
continue to cause various people to
have experiences of Himself. He
is real.
The following
discussion is meant to show that such
an experience alone, in and of itself,
cannot be seen as adequate support for
this view of God—not by anyone who
thinks they have experienced God, nor
by anyone who thinks various other
people have done so.
Our
discussion begins with a summary of
research by the distinguished
anthropologist T.M. Luhrmann (2012)
that seeks to "explain to
nonbelievers" how certain Pentecostals
"come to experience God as real" by
virtue of speaking in specific
prayerful ways. Luhrmann's
explanation is clear and
compelling. However, neither it
nor those experiences prove their
object is real in the sense of
existing independently of the
experiences in which it appears.
The Pentecostal experiences do not
prove this any more than do the
ecstasies of those who think they
experience God while influenced by
psycho-active drugs such as LSD or
psilocybin.
Although
neither type of experience proves
God's independent existence, some
philosophers think it remains possible
that God does exist independently and
appears in both types of
experience. While appreciating
this possibility, we argue that faith,
in addition to any experience of God,
is necessary for regarding Him as
actually independent of that
experience, as existing when not
experienced.
Experiences of
God Induced by Pentecostal Prayer
Luhrmann
participated both as a researcher and
as a congregant for two years apiece
in two Vineyard Christian Fellowship
churches; one in Chicago and one in
California. She describes the
roughly 600 members as ordinary,
decent, educated, smart. Most
were middle class, but some were
wealthy, and others were poor.
Most were white, but some were
minorities. All yearned
for "more" in life, especially
regarding love, peace, and
self-control. All yearned to
gain these things through faith in God
combined with prayers spoken to Him in
a three-part "technique."
In this
technique, speakers first imagine God
as "present" while delivering prayers
of adoration, confession,
thanksgiving, and supplication.
According to Luhrmann, many adult
Pentecostal speakers can imagine
successfully in this way, often by
behaving as children do with imaginary
friends—for example, setting out a cup
of coffee for God while drinking their
own during morning prayer with
Him. Second, speakers imagine
they are not imagining; God as
"internally" present in imagination is
construed as "external" to it, as
independent of it. Apparently,
Pentecostals are sometimes able to
take advantage of a "participatory
theory of mind" in which, Luhrmann
writes, they "recognize God's presence
in what they had previously
experienced as a fuzzy mental blur"
(60), in "seeing, hearing, and
touching above all" (161). At
such moments, they treat these things
as caused by God, develop a responsive
prayer to Him; and then await further
spontaneous and unexpected thoughts or
sensations. Third, they "allow
this sense of God […] to discipline
their thoughts and emotions"; in
particular, those who pray in this way
sometimes feel that "God looks after
them and loves them unconditionally"
(xxi). Biblical prophets might
be understood as having prayed with
techniques similar to this.
Luhrmann
describes the technique as inherently
ambiguous and only rarely successful
in making God seem present in a
speaker's conscious awareness.
Prayers that did seem successful
typically concerned another person for
whom the prayer was delivered: "In
practice, the prayers that really
persuaded people of God's speaking to
them in their minds were prayers for
other people, in which the ordinary
thoughts that floated into their mind
during the prayer seemed uncannily
appropriate for the person about whom
they prayed" (49). Not just
appropriate but sometimes effective:
they changed "the listener's
perspective from that of a scared
human looking out at life's challenges
to that of a creator God looking down
with love" (115). In short, a
sense of God as present was found from
the "fuzzy mental blur" that inspired
those of a Pentecostal speaker's
prayers that themselves changed a
listener's perspective from fear to
comfort.
Dan
A'Ambrosio (2014) describes a
confirming type of experience, the
subject of this one being only the
object of prayer, i.e., the person
prayed for. Fuller Smith, a
young baseball coach at the University
of Mississippi, was at an away game
with Donna Holdiness, who led the
team's booster club. At the
game, police told her that her husband
had been struck and killed by a
motorist while riding his bicycle.
Smith told her she had to call her
son.
"I
said, 'Fuller, I can't,' " Holdiness
remembered. "He said, 'I will
dial the number.' He handed me
the phone and got down on his knees
and started praying for the strength
to tell my son his father was
killed. It was the most
amazing thing. I was calm,
clear, and in control. I felt
the arms of God almighty around me
as that boy was on his knees praying
strength for me." (44)
For Holdiness as well as for the
Pentecostals, speech inspired a person
to experience God. For
Holdiness, it was the one hearing the
speech. For Pentecostals, it was
the speaker; and perhaps a hearer as
well.
Experiences of
God Induced by
Changes in Brain Activity
There are two
especially good reasons why
speech-inspired experiences of God do
not prove his independent
existence.
First, Wilder
Penfield (1958) and subsequent brain
scientists have shown that direct
electrical brain stimulation suffices
to produce not just the fuzzy mental
blurs associated with God's presence
for Pentecostals but also visual and
tactile images that cohere almost as
well as do what is seen and what is
felt of a normal object.
In other
words, the experiences of God as
present during Pentecostal prayer
might result simply because such
prayer causes relevant changes in a
person's brain activity, much as does
meditation. But the changes in
brain activity, not an independent
God, might be solely responsible for
those visual and tactile images (as
skeptics assume also happens when God
appears in deep meditation).
The second
reason concerns Walter Pahnke's (1966)
double-blind Marsh Chapel experiment
with psilocybin. Within an
intensely religious atmosphere of
music, readings, prayers, and personal
meditation, almost all of the divinity
students who ingested psilocybin
reported an experience of God.
This was not true of the students who
ingested a placebo. Most of the
psilocybin-affected students
interviewed six months later reported
"that the experience had […] motivated
them to appreciate more deeply the
meaning of their lives, to gain […]
more tolerance, more real love, and
more authenticity as a person by
virtue of being more open and more
one's true self with others […] need
for service to others." R. R.
Griffiths and his collaborators (2006)
report similar results from a
follow-up psilocybin experiment.
In particular, the psilocybin-affected
experiences they studied "had marked
similarities to classic mystical
experiences and which were rated by
volunteers as having substantial
personal meaning and spiritual
significance," producing "sustained
positive changes in attitudes and
behavior that were consistent with
changes rated by friends and family,"
including "[a]ltruistic/positive
social effects." (1) In sum,
psilocybin can produce experiences of
God markedly similar to those
classically associated with a view of
God as real, as existing independently
of experiences of Him.
This said, we
know that many objects of
psilocybin-induced experiences in
secular environments are not
independent of those experiences—that
is, that they are
hallucinations. We can see for
ourselves that a red fire hydrant does
not really change color in an
environment we share, that imaginary
people do not really appear and
interact with things we see and feel,
and that time does not really speed up
or slow down except at extreme
velocities. Skeptics conclude
that the God experienced by someone
under the influence of psilocybin
likewise does not exist independently
of those experiences, but results from
changes in brain activity caused by a
psycho-active drug, ceasing to exist
when not experienced.
This result
is relevant for understanding the God
in experiences produced by Pentecostal
prayer. In both cases,
God-related experiences can be viewed
as resulting for people who use one or
another technique to alter the
activity of their brains. For
Pentecostals, it is prayer spoken with
a specific technique; for the divinity
students, it was ingesting
psilocybin. Both types of
experience can be viewed as resulting
from unusual brain activity, as was
true for the experiences that resulted
from Penfield's direct electrical
brain stimulations. If we assume
that alterations of brain activities
are responsible for the religious
experiences, however, their objects
should not be understood as existing
independently of the experiences. (2)
Rather, these objects should be
viewed as ceasing to exist entirely
when not existing as objects of
experience.
In Addition to
Experience, Faith Is Necessary for
Regarding the Supreme Being in any
Religious Experience as Having
Independent Existence
Prior to the
psilocybin experiments by Pahnke,
James B. Pratt (1941) had assumed, for
the sake of argument, that scientists
would eventually develop a completely
naturalistic explanation for
experiences of God. Scientists
would identify exactly which brain
activities yield these experiences,
and induce them with purely natural
methods—psycho-active drugs, for
example. As a result, Pratt
granted that experiences of God do not
prove His existence as independent of
such experiences. But Pratt then
observed that God might still be understood
this way. Specifically, He
might be understood as having created
humans so that His specifically
intervening grace would eventually not
be necessary for His appearing to us
in experience. Rather, He has
blessed us with the sort of bodies we
can manipulate so as to achieve that
experience without His
intervention.
The main
problem with this otherwise intriguing
possibility is that the objects of
religious experiences in different
cultures have incompatible
features. Such an
incompatibility implies that at least
one of the objects in these
manifestations of the divine cannot be
real in the sense of existing
independently of experience, existing
when not experienced. This is
interestingly true when the results of
Judeo-Christian prayer are compared
with those of traditional Ghanaian
animists. Benjamin D. Sommer
(2009) raised this type of point in
explicating the distinction between
monotheism and polytheism.
Sommer
explains the need for explication by
observing that Judaism and
Christianity are importantly like
polytheism. Specifically, all
posit the existence not just of the
physical universe and the Supreme
Being who created it but also of
certain subordinate non-physical
entities that help Him guide the
universe.
For Jews
and Christians these are angels.
For polytheists they are, among other
things, deities and the life-forces of
departed ancestors. Angels have
relevantly less power than deities and
life-forces, however. Sommer
observes this is why only the Supreme
Being for Jews and Christians should
be understood monotheistically.
The
Judeo-Christian Supreme Being invites
angels to intercede with Him on behalf
of humans to change the physical
world. However, He does not allow
angels to make those changes without
His explicit permission. (3)
Only the Supreme Being can
independently change the physical
world in non-physical ways.
Thus, Jews and Christians sometimes
"pray to various heavenly beings to
intercede on their behalf with the one
God in whom all power ultimately
resides" (Sommer 147). But Jews
and Christians do not pray for angels
to independently change the physical
world themselves.
In contrast,
Sommer observes that polytheistic
"people pray to multiple deities
because of a belief that multiple
deities have their own power to effect
change" (147). In other words,
polytheists believe that, in addition
to the Supreme Being, there are many
subordinate non-physical entities that
are unconstrained by the physical laws
that normally constrain the movements
of people and other physical
objects. Ghanaian animists, for
example, believe this is true
regarding the life-forces of departed
ancestors, especially royal
ones. Thus a Ghanaian animist
might explain "a mysterious malady in
terms of, say, the wrath of the
ancestors" (Wiredu 51). While
"they derive ultimately from Onyame,"
the Supreme Being, the life-forces of
departed ancestors have "mystical
powers" (Gyekye 73), powers that can
sometimes be "causes of action and
change in the world" (Gyekye 79).
Clearly,
however, a Supreme Being cannot
both allow some
subordinate non-physical entities to
intervene autonomously in physical
events while also preventing any
of them from doing so. At this
point of discussion, then, either the
Supreme Being experienced through
animistic prayer cannot be viewed as
existing independently of that
experience, or the Supreme Being
experienced through Judeo-Christian
prayer cannot be so viewed.
Unfortunately, the checking procedures
that ordinarily establish the real
independence of the objects of
perceptual experience are not
available for judging experiences in
which God appears. In
particular, we cannot judge such
objects on the basis of predictions
about their future behavior that can
be seen as well as felt by any
relevantly placed observer. The
reason is that neither the Supreme
Being of Judeo-Christianity nor that
of animism satisfies these
conditions. Indeed, no object of
religious experience can be
established as independently existing
in the way independent existence is
ordinarily established. In
addition to experience, something else
is necessary for viewing the Supreme
Being in any religious experience as
having independent existence—faith,
for example.
On the face
of things, it is not surprising that
faith is necessary for Christians with
respect to the Supreme Being.
While different Christian traditions
provide different ways of
understanding faith, all accept it as
necessary for grasping the deepest
truths about the Supreme Being.
But the need for faith in addition to
experience of the Supreme Being for
regarding Him as real, as independent,
does change a common way of
understanding the authority of
Scripture. Commonly, Scripture
is understood as authoritative because
its authors are regarded as inspired
by the Supreme Being who was
independent of the experiences He
inspired them to have while writing
Scripture. Given the above
argument, however, faith in addition
to experience was necessary even for
the authors of Scripture to view the
Supreme Being as independent of their
experiences of Him. In other
words, contemporary faith is based in
part on ancient faith, not just on
ancient events. This might seem
a little surprising. (4)
Notes
(1) This was not true of the
Pentecostals studied by
Luhrmann. Indeed, her index
contains no entry for "altruism,"
"positive social effects,"
"tolerance," "authenticity," or, for
that matter, "charity" or
"compassion."" The entry for "love"
refers only to God as "unconditional
love" and to the practice of "feeling
loved."
(2) An
objection to this line of argument is
that it implies an absurdity.
One could object that all experiences,
even those of the ordinary perceived
world, result from brain activity;
thus, if we reject the independence of
the objects of religious experiences
because they result from brain
activity, we must also reject the
independent existence of the ordinary
objects of normal perceptual
experiences. Such a rejection
would seem absurd.
To explicate John
Locke's (1690) famous theory of
representative realism, however, J. L.
Mackie (1976) argues this is exactly
what we should do. A normally
perceived object should be understood
as identical with the perceptions of
it; and so nonexistent when not
perceived. To account for
correlations between seen objects and
felt objects that evolve in
predictable ways, Mackie introduces
Locke's concept of material substance,
now construed as groups of individual
molecules. Groups of molecules
cause us to perceive the objects we do
while remaining entirely distinct from
them. Their remaining distinct
explains why the objects they cause us
to see and to feel at different times
are so well correlated even though not
continuously existing. However,
the groups of molecules that cause us
to perceive an object are distinct
from it, and the individual molecules
that compose this group do not compose
that object.
This way of
thinking is obviously strange and
different from the commonsense theory
that perceived objects cause us to
perceive themselves as they exist
independently of perception.
However, C. W. K. Mundle (1971) and
Amanda Gefter (2016) summarize some of
the reasons why many neuroscientists
now prefer representative realism to
the commonsense theory of
perception. The present author
(1990) used Mackie's interpretation to
explain how representative realism
applies to religious experiences
specifically.
(3) In note 9
of his Appendix, Sommer supports this
interpretation of Christian angels
with the research of scholars focused
especially on Deut. 4.19 and 32.8,
Exodus 20.3, and Leviticus 18.25.
(4) My
thanks to Norm Robertson, an old
friend who provided helpful guidance
at several stages in this article’s
development. Thanks also to the
Editorial Advisory Committee, whose
advice about the penultimate draft
improved the article’s
structure. Of course, any
remaining defects are my
responsibility alone.
Works Cited
A'Ambrosio, Dan. 2014. "A
Tale of the Trace." Adventure
Cyclist (June): 42-44.
English, Parker. 1990.
"Representative Realism and Absolute
Reality." International
Journal for Philosophy of Religion
23: 127-145.
Gefter, Amanda. 2016. "The
Case Against Reality." The
Atlantic.com (25 April).
http://www.theatlantic.com/science
archive/2016/04/the-illusion-of-reality/479559/
retrieved 5 January 2017]
R. R. Griffiths & W. A. Richards
& U. McCann & R. Jesse.
2006. "Psilocybin Can Occasion
Mystical-Type Experiences Having
Substantial And Sustained Personal
Meaning And Spiritual Significance."
Psychopharmacology 187 (July):
268–283.
http://www.csp.org/psilocybin/Hopkins-CSP-Psilocybin2006.pdf
retrieved 5 January 2017]
Gyekye, Kwame. 1987. An
Essay on African Philosophical
Thought: The Akan Conceptual Scheme.
Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. Reprinted by Temple
University Press: Philadelphia, 1995.
Locke, John. 1690. An
Essay Concerning Human Understanding.
Luhrmann, T.M. 2012. When
God Talks Back. NY: Alfred
A. Knopf.
Mackie, J.L. 1976. Problems
from Locke. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Mundle, C.W.K. 1971. Perception:
Facts and Theories. London:
Oxford University Press.
Pahnke, Walter. 1966. "Drugs
and Mysticism." The
International Journal of
Parapsychology Vol VIII (No. 2,
Spring): 295-313 [
https://www.erowid.org/entheogens/
journals/entheogens_journal3.shtml
retrieved 5 January 2017]
Penfield, Wilder. 1958.
"Some Mechanisms Of Consciousness
Discovered During Electrical Stimulation
Of The Brain." Proceeding of
the National Academy of Science 44
(2): 51-66.
Pratt, James B. 1941. Can
We Keep the Faith? New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Sommer, Benjamin D. 2009. The
Bodies of God and the World of Ancient
Israel. Cambridge University
Press. Kindle Edition.
Wiredu, Kwasi. 1996. Cultural
Universals and Particulars: An African
Perspective. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
About the Author
After controlling close air support as
a Marine First Lieutenant in Vietnam,
1968-69, Parker English received a
Ph.D. in philosophy from the
University of Western Ontario,
1974. He next built a log cabin
not far from Goderich, Ontario, before
felling trees for a logging camp 200
miles north of Lake Superior, 1975-77.
His first teaching job was at the
University of Calabar, Nigeria,
1983-87. He retired from Central
Connecticut State University, 2013,
having had a teaching and research
specialization in the emerging field
of African philosophy. In
addition to publishing What We
Say, Who We Are and twenty
articles or book chapters, English
co-edited African Philosophy: A
Classical Approach.
English has hiked Canada's Bruce
Trail, and canoed several of its
wilderness rivers. Still an
active cyclist, he has covered more
than 10,000 miles bike-packing,
including 800 honeymoon miles with his
wife Nancy seven years ago. He
aspires to competency with his new
flatwater kayak.
"God in Experience" was presented to
the Portsmouth club on January 11,
2016.